Hume and the Standard of Taste

1
00:00:00,060 --> 00:00:10,740
Today, we're going to discuss Hume and his views on the Senate of Taste and with this lecture.

2
00:00:10,740 --> 00:00:15,840
It's the first lecture in which we're going to be discussing beauty at great length.

3
00:00:15,840 --> 00:00:22,200
And we'll also be covering this in the Kant lecture, which I think is probably going to extend over to lectures.

4
00:00:22,200 --> 00:00:26,670
I don't think it's realistic to do a critique of judgement in just one lecture.

5
00:00:26,670 --> 00:00:30,720
So tomorrow we'll do count as well. And that will probably continue into next week.

6
00:00:30,720 --> 00:00:36,840
And a likelihood, if any of you have done ethics, particularly better ethics,

7
00:00:36,840 --> 00:00:42,450
you'll be already familiar with some of the issues that are going to arise here.

8
00:00:42,450 --> 00:00:53,340
So one of the common questions in philosophy about both moral value and aesthetic value is about the reality of it and the nature of it.

9
00:00:53,340 --> 00:01:02,640
And a lot of very well worked out positions in media ethics that you can take on these questions.

10
00:01:02,640 --> 00:01:15,450
It's worth pointing out that regarding Hume, that he is not least declaims, doubting the existence of beautiful objects of beauty.

11
00:01:15,450 --> 00:01:23,400
His claim is a claim about the nature of beauty. And so I'm going to begin with some of his background views on beauty,

12
00:01:23,400 --> 00:01:29,430
because his views on the nature of beauty are going to be important for understanding his views on the standard of taste.

13
00:01:29,430 --> 00:01:35,040
Now, whether he can maintain this view that he's not dead and the existence of reality of beauty,

14
00:01:35,040 --> 00:01:40,440
while alongside his view on its nature, is another question.

15
00:01:40,440 --> 00:01:46,680
But I think we can distinguish between three important theses that emerge in humans, other work, particularly in his essay.

16
00:01:46,680 --> 00:01:52,230
The Sceptic and in some of his moral writings and other writings.

17
00:01:52,230 --> 00:02:02,910
The first is this claim that you get stated in various ways that beauty is not equality objects have in themselves.

18
00:02:02,910 --> 00:02:07,500
Now, this is a very common view, the 18th century standard of taste.

19
00:02:07,500 --> 00:02:15,990
He doesn't even repeat in the arguments for it. He does give some arguments for it in his essay, The Sceptic.

20
00:02:15,990 --> 00:02:26,700
And if any of you are familiar with Hume's views on moral value, you'll be reminded in some ways of his take on that, in his views on beauty.

21
00:02:26,700 --> 00:02:32,250
And similarly, there are similarities between his views on beauty and his views on cause and necessity.

22
00:02:32,250 --> 00:02:40,440
He runs abbreviated versions in effect of some of the arguments he runs for those matters on beauty.

23
00:02:40,440 --> 00:02:49,590
So one of the considerations, in fact, the main consideration he really offers in sceptic is the thought that you can know or explain all of

24
00:02:49,590 --> 00:02:56,100
the qualities that a thing has without either knowing or having explained anything about its beauty.

25
00:02:56,100 --> 00:02:59,400
So he gives a number of examples of this kind.

26
00:02:59,400 --> 00:03:08,310
He talks about the circle and says Euclid has mentioned all the properties of the circle, but has said nothing of its beauty.

27
00:03:08,310 --> 00:03:12,000
The reason is evident. Beauty is not a property of the circle.

28
00:03:12,000 --> 00:03:17,850
It doesn't consist in any of the relations between the parts or anything that Euclid has picked out.

29
00:03:17,850 --> 00:03:20,970
Similarly, in his enquiry concerning the principles of morals,

30
00:03:20,970 --> 00:03:29,130
he talks about architecture and he mentions the architectural treatises written at that time which talk about

31
00:03:29,130 --> 00:03:34,440
the kinds of relations that each of the parts of the orders of architecture have to have to one another.

32
00:03:34,440 --> 00:03:40,260
And he says, if you ask Palladio or Parro, these architectural writers,

33
00:03:40,260 --> 00:03:47,460
where is the beauty in all of these relations, they'd say it's not in any of them.

34
00:03:47,460 --> 00:03:54,090
And where is it? Well, Hume says naturally it is in the sentiment of the person who looks at these things.

35
00:03:54,090 --> 00:04:06,950
So this is on the grounds that it's not until you feel a sentiment I'm looking at of things, properties that you become aware of its beauty.

36
00:04:06,950 --> 00:04:13,560
Scuse me. And therefore, as Hume puts it in various ways, beauty lies in the sentiments.

37
00:04:13,560 --> 00:04:22,320
Beauty consists in an agreeable sentiment. These are somewhat obscure ways of putting things because taken at their word,

38
00:04:22,320 --> 00:04:31,320
it sounds a bit like he's saying that it's sentiments that are beautiful, not objects, but he never draws that implication out.

39
00:04:31,320 --> 00:04:36,660
So it's a little bit difficult to understand quite how this claims to be understood.

40
00:04:36,660 --> 00:04:42,030
The claim that beauty lies in the sentiment doesn't mean beauty is a property of the sentiment.

41
00:04:42,030 --> 00:04:49,290
Somehow it consists in an agreeable sentiment. What is clear is that we don't notice that something's beautiful until we have a sentiment and

42
00:04:49,290 --> 00:04:54,480
that's supposed to be evidence in addition to the other considerations that it's not a property.

43
00:04:54,480 --> 00:04:58,980
Objects have in themselves, nevertheless.

44
00:04:58,980 --> 00:05:07,350
And this is the third. Point Hume is well aware that we think of beauty as a property that objects have in themselves.

45
00:05:07,350 --> 00:05:15,990
And this third point has to do with what is related to what he says about cause and necessity as well.

46
00:05:15,990 --> 00:05:25,650
So he phrases it a number of ways, one of which is on the back of the handout.

47
00:05:25,650 --> 00:05:32,880
So the first quotation and this from the sceptic objects have absolutely no worth or value in themselves.

48
00:05:32,880 --> 00:05:37,120
They derive their worth merely from the passion who is not sensible.

49
00:05:37,120 --> 00:05:41,100
The power and glory and vengeance are not desirable of themselves,

50
00:05:41,100 --> 00:05:47,820
but derive all their value from the structure of human passions, which begets a desire towards such particular pursuits.

51
00:05:47,820 --> 00:05:52,920
But with regard to beauty, either natural or moral, the case is commonly supposed to be different.

52
00:05:52,920 --> 00:05:57,060
The agreeable quality is thought to lie in the object, not in the sentiment,

53
00:05:57,060 --> 00:06:06,150
and that merely because the sentiment is not so turbulent and violent as to distinguish itself in an evident manner from the perception of the object.

54
00:06:06,150 --> 00:06:15,870
So this is one claim he makes, partly by way of explanation of why we think that beauty is a property of the object itself,

55
00:06:15,870 --> 00:06:19,920
namely that the sentiment in which it consists is a very calm one.

56
00:06:19,920 --> 00:06:26,430
And he thinks that we're confusing that Tom sentiment with a perception of something in the object and in later work.

57
00:06:26,430 --> 00:06:31,980
He elaborates this notion, and this is in the second quotation from the enquiry,

58
00:06:31,980 --> 00:06:36,780
The distinct boundaries and offices of Reason and Taste are easily ascertained.

59
00:06:36,780 --> 00:06:43,650
The former conveys the knowledge of truth and falsehood. The latter gives the sentiment of beauty and deformity, vice and virtue.

60
00:06:43,650 --> 00:06:48,690
The one discovers objects as they really stand in nature without additions and diminution.

61
00:06:48,690 --> 00:06:56,460
The other has a productive faculty and gilding or staining all natural objects with the colours borrowed from internal sentiment raises in a manner,

62
00:06:56,460 --> 00:07:06,960
a new creation. So it seems like what he's saying is that we in some sense project onto objects when we find them beautiful.

63
00:07:06,960 --> 00:07:13,530
So it's not just the claim that beauty is not a property, the object, or that it lies in the sentiment, whatever that amounts to,

64
00:07:13,530 --> 00:07:23,550
but that in addition, we sort of Project Guild or Stane objects with the colours borrowed from that sentiment.

65
00:07:23,550 --> 00:07:28,020
Now, this sort of view raised a number of questions.

66
00:07:28,020 --> 00:07:36,580
I mean, it can probably be best understood by analogy with what he says about cause and necessity.

67
00:07:36,580 --> 00:07:43,510
So he says, we often think that necessity resides in objects that stand in causal relations as well.

68
00:07:43,510 --> 00:07:50,860
Even though our idea of necessity just comes from our feeling of expectation, we get when we see an object of one kind.

69
00:07:50,860 --> 00:07:56,110
Appear that has always been followed by an object of another kind.

70
00:07:56,110 --> 00:08:01,210
When that happens, we have a tendency to imagine an object of the other kind.

71
00:08:01,210 --> 00:08:04,030
And it's this inclination or tendency,

72
00:08:04,030 --> 00:08:17,290
this feeling that we project onto the object and that accounts for our view that necessity is a property of the object.

73
00:08:17,290 --> 00:08:26,400
I take it that he thinks some sort of mechanism like that is at work here.

74
00:08:26,400 --> 00:08:37,020
And in each case, it sort of raises the question, how can you say that there is some reality to beauty in these cases?

75
00:08:37,020 --> 00:08:45,510
So it looks like he's not willing to say in the causal case that necessity is a property of a tendency, for example.

76
00:08:45,510 --> 00:08:50,520
And of course, it's not a property object, something we project onto it.

77
00:08:50,520 --> 00:08:53,610
So it doesn't seem to be a property of anything.

78
00:08:53,610 --> 00:09:01,160
And likewise with beauty, he doesn't and he shouldn't say that it's only sentiments that have the property of being beautiful.

79
00:09:01,160 --> 00:09:08,400
But he explicitly denies as well that it's objects that have the property of being beautiful.

80
00:09:08,400 --> 00:09:16,710
What is true is that there's an agreeableness to the sentiment and that kind of sentiment gets projected onto the object.

81
00:09:16,710 --> 00:09:21,780
But that's rather different from anything ending up with the property of beauty.

82
00:09:21,780 --> 00:09:26,880
So visibly, there's at least the appearance of a difficulty here.

83
00:09:26,880 --> 00:09:35,880
And it's not so clear that he can say what he does say in the third quotation, which again is from the sceptic.

84
00:09:35,880 --> 00:09:39,750
So he says, we're not afraid of appearing too philosophical.

85
00:09:39,750 --> 00:09:45,020
I should remind my reader of that famous doctrine supposed to be fully proved in modern times.

86
00:09:45,020 --> 00:09:49,170
The tastes and colours and all other sensible qualities light on in the bodies.

87
00:09:49,170 --> 00:09:54,000
But merely in the senses. The case is the same with beauty and deformity.

88
00:09:54,000 --> 00:09:58,950
Virtue invites this doctrine, however, and this is the Chebet takes off.

89
00:09:58,950 --> 00:10:05,310
No more reality from the takes off, no more from the reality of the latter qualities than from that of the former.

90
00:10:05,310 --> 00:10:09,000
No need to give any umbrage to either your critics or more or less.

91
00:10:09,000 --> 00:10:15,040
The colours were allowed to lie only in the eye with dyers or painters ever be less regarded or esteemed.

92
00:10:15,040 --> 00:10:20,070
There is insufficient uniformity in the senses and feelings of mankind to make all these qualities,

93
00:10:20,070 --> 00:10:24,840
the objects of art and reasoning, and to have the greatest influence on life and manners.

94
00:10:24,840 --> 00:10:31,530
And as it is certain that the discovery above mentioned in natural philosophy makes no alteration on action and conduct.

95
00:10:31,530 --> 00:10:42,210
Why should a like discovery, moral philosophy make any alteration? So this is a comparison that is going to come back to the standard of taste between

96
00:10:42,210 --> 00:10:50,250
beauty on the one hand and secondary qualities like colour and flavour on the other.

97
00:10:50,250 --> 00:10:55,230
But there's a couple of peculiarities of what he said about what he says in this passage.

98
00:10:55,230 --> 00:11:01,020
So when the quote he gives here, I don't know who it's from.

99
00:11:01,020 --> 00:11:09,780
If it from anybody that tastes in colours and all of the sensible qualities lie not in the bodies, but merely in the senses.

100
00:11:09,780 --> 00:11:17,610
Locke famously described colours, flavours of secondary qualities as opposed to primary qualities.

101
00:11:17,610 --> 00:11:20,970
But Locke did not deny that objects are coloured.

102
00:11:20,970 --> 00:11:30,730
What Locke said was that the colour of objects is a power to produce an idea or might more accurately be described as a visual impression in us.

103
00:11:30,730 --> 00:11:38,370
And that visual impression has certain appearance properties that don't resemble anything in the object.

104
00:11:38,370 --> 00:11:42,420
But that's very different from saying that there's no colour in the object, because in Locke's view,

105
00:11:42,420 --> 00:11:47,040
colour in the object is a power to produce a visual impression that has certain

106
00:11:47,040 --> 00:11:53,580
appearance properties that don't themselves resemble anything in the object.

107
00:11:53,580 --> 00:11:59,610
So the thing he quotes here would not be an accurate representation of Locke's view.

108
00:11:59,610 --> 00:12:04,920
Locke's view is there's nothing resembling the quality of our visual impression in the object.

109
00:12:04,920 --> 00:12:06,990
It's not that objects aren't coloured.

110
00:12:06,990 --> 00:12:17,850
It's just that what it is for them to be coloured is for them to have the power to produce this kind of visual impression and this sort of view.

111
00:12:17,850 --> 00:12:24,420
Now, I'm not saying he has to follow Locke, obviously. Maybe he's talking about a different view of secondary qualities.

112
00:12:24,420 --> 00:12:33,090
But at least with Locke, you can point to something that is unambiguously describable as coloured with Hume.

113
00:12:33,090 --> 00:12:37,900
It's not so clear because if you don't want to say the sentiment is beautiful.

114
00:12:37,900 --> 00:12:43,830
And if you don't want to say the object is beautiful and it's not clear if you don't want it to be a beauty is in the object,

115
00:12:43,830 --> 00:12:50,240
I should say it's not quite clear how we should understand this and how he can maintain that beauty,

116
00:12:50,240 --> 00:12:55,230
that this view takes nothing off the reality of beautiful objects of beauty.

117
00:12:55,230 --> 00:13:06,840
That is OK. So this is the background to his essay on the standard of taste.

118
00:13:06,840 --> 00:13:09,960
And one reason why Hume's view on the standard of taste is attractive to a lot

119
00:13:09,960 --> 00:13:18,390
of people is that it seems to offer a way to reconcile two opposing views.

120
00:13:18,390 --> 00:13:24,930
So the first is the view that out there in the world, there's no values.

121
00:13:24,930 --> 00:13:35,310
No beauty. No goodness. Cetera. Things don't have those qualities in themselves, and yet you can get these things wrong.

122
00:13:35,310 --> 00:13:48,110
People can be wrong about what and right. That is, there can be standards about whether something is beautiful or good.

123
00:13:48,110 --> 00:13:59,480
So he seems to offer us a way which is attract a lot of people, both in aesthetics and in ethics, of having both of these positions.

124
00:13:59,480 --> 00:14:05,150
The denial of the reality of these sort of metaphysically dubious or spooky,

125
00:14:05,150 --> 00:14:16,240
according to some properties like beauty and goodness out there in the world, along with the maintenance of standards for judgements of these things.

126
00:14:16,240 --> 00:14:20,080
Now, the motivation to Hume identifies for seeking the standard of taste.

127
00:14:20,080 --> 00:14:26,560
Is the observation that people frequently disagree about the beauty of an object.

128
00:14:26,560 --> 00:14:33,100
So what it is for them to disagree, of course, is for them to have different sentiments about same object.

129
00:14:33,100 --> 00:14:35,260
And he really stresses this at the start.

130
00:14:35,260 --> 00:14:44,020
If you look across cultures and within cultures and within your own social circle, you will find widely divergent views,

131
00:14:44,020 --> 00:14:52,930
very divergent sentiments about which objects are beautiful or whether some particular object is beautiful.

132
00:14:52,930 --> 00:15:02,950
Furthermore, it's not just that we differ, but that we argue. So we are inclined to condemn sentiments that disagree with our own.

133
00:15:02,950 --> 00:15:07,420
And this naturally makes us wonder or at least makes them more reflective amongst us.

134
00:15:07,420 --> 00:15:15,160
Wonder if there is some way of justifying our sentiment.

135
00:15:15,160 --> 00:15:22,480
If there's some way, some grounds for condemning sentiments that differ from our own.

136
00:15:22,480 --> 00:15:32,950
And this is what Hume attempts to provide. What he says a standard of taste is, is the following.

137
00:15:32,950 --> 00:15:39,370
He says it is a rule by which the various sentiments of men may be reconciled.

138
00:15:39,370 --> 00:15:45,580
At least a decision afforded confirming one sentiment and condemning another.

139
00:15:45,580 --> 00:15:57,940
So ideally, it's a way of ending these disputes. At minimum, it should be a way of figuring out who's right in each of them.

140
00:15:57,940 --> 00:16:07,330
That's the ambition. Now, it's worth noting here that he's not saying I'm trying to define beauty.

141
00:16:07,330 --> 00:16:16,300
Now, I don't mean that he wouldn't accept this as his definition of beauty or say that this is what it is for something to be beautiful.

142
00:16:16,300 --> 00:16:20,250
That is at least the thing that he's going to go on to say.

143
00:16:20,250 --> 00:16:28,570
But it's worth noting that he wouldn't need to do that in order to get this thing a rule enabling us to figure out who is right.

144
00:16:28,570 --> 00:16:36,400
All you need, then, all you'd need for that was some reliable detector of beauty or of condemnable sentiment.

145
00:16:36,400 --> 00:16:42,040
Some criterion by which you can tell that one side is wrong, the other side is right.

146
00:16:42,040 --> 00:16:49,840
Not something as ambitious as a definition of beauty as again, I'm not saying this is not a definition of beauty in his view,

147
00:16:49,840 --> 00:16:55,390
but what he explicitly says is that it's a way of reconciling these views,

148
00:16:55,390 --> 00:16:58,780
a way of finding a way to condemn certain sentiments,

149
00:16:58,780 --> 00:17:09,240
confirm others that can be important at certain points when we're thinking about what kinds of criticisms him is subject to.

150
00:17:09,240 --> 00:17:18,290
OK, well, immediately having presented this possibility, he then considers an objection to the very possibility of finding a standard of taste.

151
00:17:18,290 --> 00:17:26,110
And he says this is an objection drawn from common sense. In fact, it's drawn from a number of philosophical considerations as well.

152
00:17:26,110 --> 00:17:29,950
And it's worth when you're thinking about this objection, being aware of which parts of it.

153
00:17:29,950 --> 00:17:39,030
Hume accepts and which parts he does not. People often read this as misread this as something that Hume accepts wholesale.

154
00:17:39,030 --> 00:17:46,690
He accepts a lot of it, but not all of it. Now, the objection basically is that it's not possible to condemn sentiments.

155
00:17:46,690 --> 00:17:51,760
This rule that's supposed to enable us to do this therefore can't be found.

156
00:17:51,760 --> 00:17:58,000
And the reasons given. I think you can identify at least three in this passage.

157
00:17:58,000 --> 00:18:06,040
The first of which is that sentiment's cannot be condemned for misrepresenting the world.

158
00:18:06,040 --> 00:18:12,010
So sentiment's online judgements don't represent the world as being a certain way.

159
00:18:12,010 --> 00:18:18,340
So if you judge that the cat is on the mat, that represents the world's being a certain way.

160
00:18:18,340 --> 00:18:24,010
And if the cat's not on the mat, it misrepresents the world. But sentiments aren't like that.

161
00:18:24,010 --> 00:18:36,490
Sentiments aren't representational. So they can't misrepresent the world and therefore they can't be condemned for misrepresenting the world.

162
00:18:36,490 --> 00:18:47,440
Another reason they can't be condemned is they cannot be condemned for marking a relation between the mind and the object that's not there.

163
00:18:47,440 --> 00:18:53,230
So although sentiments don't represent the way things are, they do mark or signal,

164
00:18:53,230 --> 00:18:59,710
as he puts it, a relation or conformity between the mind and the object.

165
00:18:59,710 --> 00:19:05,860
But of course, if the sentiment occurs at all, then that relation exists.

166
00:19:05,860 --> 00:19:11,860
And so they can't mark a relation in this way. That's not actually there.

167
00:19:11,860 --> 00:19:17,920
And so you can't condemn them for marking a relation. That's not actually there.

168
00:19:17,920 --> 00:19:20,980
Now, those two points are true of sentiments, generally,

169
00:19:20,980 --> 00:19:32,720
sentiments of beauty in particular cannot be condemned for occurring in the absence of beauty in the object.

170
00:19:32,720 --> 00:19:42,680
Because beauty doesn't exist in the objects as we discuss. So all sentiments of beauty occur in the absence of beauty and the object.

171
00:19:42,680 --> 00:19:45,920
And moreover, beauty exists in a sentiment.

172
00:19:45,920 --> 00:19:53,660
And so it's not a bad thing that all these sentiments of beauty occur in the absence of beauty in the object.

173
00:19:53,660 --> 00:19:59,420
They can't be condemned for occurring in the absence of beauty in the object.

174
00:19:59,420 --> 00:20:07,130
So they can't be condemned on those grounds either. So it seems like it's not possible at all to condemn sentiments.

175
00:20:07,130 --> 00:20:11,090
Now, as I say, Huma represents this as a sort of objection from common sense.

176
00:20:11,090 --> 00:20:17,390
It's the view that Taste's can't be disputed about.

177
00:20:17,390 --> 00:20:25,580
But his reply is that it's as least as well supported by common sense to suppose that at least some sentiments can be condemned.

178
00:20:25,580 --> 00:20:32,100
And he argues from some famous examples here. He says, Anybody who would think that the miners,

179
00:20:32,100 --> 00:20:46,130
Scottish poet John Ogleby and the 17th century English puritan John Bunyan were as good as Joseph Addison and John Milton,

180
00:20:46,130 --> 00:20:53,000
or indeed who preferred them to those guys would have ridiculous and absurd sentiments.

181
00:20:53,000 --> 00:21:02,670
And that's at least as clear, he thinks, as the considerations advanced in the objection.

182
00:21:02,670 --> 00:21:08,520
Now, he's not denying a lot of what the objection sets, as I mentioned at the start.

183
00:21:08,520 --> 00:21:13,170
So he agrees that sentiments can't be condemned on any of the grounds mentioned in the objection.

184
00:21:13,170 --> 00:21:16,230
So he's not going to go there, even adds something.

185
00:21:16,230 --> 00:21:24,960
He adds that it may be that when objects are nearly equal in value and people's sentiments diverge,

186
00:21:24,960 --> 00:21:29,730
then we can't say that one side is right and one side is wrong.

187
00:21:29,730 --> 00:21:38,640
But he says it's at least clear that at least some sentiments can be condemned like these once.

188
00:21:38,640 --> 00:21:48,020
And that's at least as clear as anything presented in the objection. And so the hunt is on for a standard enabling us to do this.

189
00:21:48,020 --> 00:21:54,590
Now, famously, the standard he states is that standard of taste is the joint verdict and a verdict.

190
00:21:54,590 --> 00:22:03,800
Here is again, something based on sentiment of all critics who are free of certain obstructions.

191
00:22:03,800 --> 00:22:11,870
And we'll get into what those obstructions are in a moment. But that's the general shape of it.

192
00:22:11,870 --> 00:22:21,920
Is that standard is going to be not the mere occurrence of a sentiment, but the occurrence of a sentiment in the right kinds of people.

193
00:22:21,920 --> 00:22:27,140
And conformity with that sentiment is or lack of conformity with that sentiment.

194
00:22:27,140 --> 00:22:39,090
More to the point is what enables sentiments to be condemned. That's not exactly transparent, what his argument for this view is.

195
00:22:39,090 --> 00:22:43,410
I think you can identify two for this general view.

196
00:22:43,410 --> 00:22:49,170
And then he goes on to argue in particular for what the obstructions are.

197
00:22:49,170 --> 00:22:58,070
But the first, I think, is what I've described in the handout as the argument from Beauty's capacity to please universally.

198
00:22:58,070 --> 00:23:09,210
So a key premise for Hume is that beautiful objects can please anyone, at least have the capacity to please anyone.

199
00:23:09,210 --> 00:23:13,440
Not that they always do, in fact, but they at least have that capacity.

200
00:23:13,440 --> 00:23:20,100
And he gives a number of considerations in support of this. So one is kind of quaint.

201
00:23:20,100 --> 00:23:22,950
But I talked about the rules of composition.

202
00:23:22,950 --> 00:23:34,050
So the rules by which writing can be guided, the rules if you follow, which will enable you to write beautifully.

203
00:23:34,050 --> 00:23:42,360
He says these rules are just observations about what has pleased at all times and in all periods of history.

204
00:23:42,360 --> 00:23:48,870
In fact, if you find something, that's if you find a counterexample to them, then you have to revise the rules,

205
00:23:48,870 --> 00:23:57,420
because what they're aiming at is to get at what has pleased, you know, at all times and in all periods of history.

206
00:23:57,420 --> 00:24:03,120
That's one consideration that's supposed to suggest that beauty at least has the capacity to please universally.

207
00:24:03,120 --> 00:24:07,810
Another consideration is from examples such as Homer.

208
00:24:07,810 --> 00:24:19,670
It's one of his examples pointing out that genuinely beautiful objects have, in fact, pleased in a wide diversity of ages and cultures.

209
00:24:19,670 --> 00:24:32,230
Homer being example. And I think it's on this basis that he is convinced that beautiful works at least have this capacity to please everyone.

210
00:24:32,230 --> 00:24:34,360
He's got to face the fact, of course, that they don't.

211
00:24:34,360 --> 00:24:41,470
In fact, the very fact that he stressed at the beginning, a lot of the time, genuinely beautiful objects don't please everyone who sees them.

212
00:24:41,470 --> 00:24:43,570
And the thought is.

213
00:24:43,570 --> 00:24:54,760
So his next point is that it's just obvious that many obstructions prevent beautiful works from actually actualising this capacity.

214
00:24:54,760 --> 00:24:59,230
And again, he gives a number of points in favour of this.

215
00:24:59,230 --> 00:25:06,170
So one of them is he considers what it is that we do when we try to determine that an object is beautiful.

216
00:25:06,170 --> 00:25:10,120
It says we try and get into the right state of mind. We try and be calm.

217
00:25:10,120 --> 00:25:18,160
Pay attention to the object. Seems like we have to do a lot to prepare in order to judge an object accurately.

218
00:25:18,160 --> 00:25:29,110
That's supposed to suggest that there's loads of possible obstructions in place and we have to make sure that they're absent.

219
00:25:29,110 --> 00:25:38,350
Another reason of the view that there are lots of obstructions preventing beauty from pleasing everyone.

220
00:25:38,350 --> 00:25:40,590
Is based on the test of time.

221
00:25:40,590 --> 00:25:51,390
So we often points to the fact that the work has survived and been enjoyed in all kinds of areas as evidence that it is beautiful.

222
00:25:51,390 --> 00:25:56,340
And he thinks the reason we do this, at least this is how I read this passage,

223
00:25:56,340 --> 00:26:04,620
is to see whether it still pleases once fashion, prejudice and authority fallen away.

224
00:26:04,620 --> 00:26:11,820
That's why the test of time is a good test of beauty, is that it's a test to see whether it pleases,

225
00:26:11,820 --> 00:26:18,810
even when these various obstructions have fallen away.

226
00:26:18,810 --> 00:26:26,540
That, again, seems to imply that there are lots of obstructions to beauteous capacity to please everyone.

227
00:26:26,540 --> 00:26:36,770
And so I think that it's on this basis that he concludes the standard of taste has got to be the sentiment of everyone free of certain obstructions,

228
00:26:36,770 --> 00:26:47,210
because everyone who is free of these obstructions will like it can please everyone, but only provided they're free from the obstructions.

229
00:26:47,210 --> 00:26:59,030
Now, the second argument that I detect in this essay is based on further comparison with secondary qualities in the essay,

230
00:26:59,030 --> 00:27:10,360
particularly colours and flavours. So this I take it to be an argument by analogy, colours and flavours.

231
00:27:10,360 --> 00:27:17,270
He says, if you think about it, are in all relevant respects, similar to beauty.

232
00:27:17,270 --> 00:27:21,710
So as we saw, colours and flavours are not qualities that objects have in themselves.

233
00:27:21,710 --> 00:27:31,120
That's a key thing. Colours and flavours are in the mind.

234
00:27:31,120 --> 00:27:38,620
And this is particularly important. Some people are not qualified to give verdicts about colours and flavours despite

235
00:27:38,620 --> 00:27:44,380
the fact that they're not in the object and that they're only in the mind.

236
00:27:44,380 --> 00:27:51,580
Examples. Someone with jaundice. Not in a position to judge concerning colours.

237
00:27:51,580 --> 00:28:00,190
Someone with a fever. Not in a position to judge concerning flavours in these relevantly similar cases.

238
00:28:00,190 --> 00:28:11,890
The standard of judgement is the response of a person free of certain obstructions.

239
00:28:11,890 --> 00:28:27,620
So with healthy eyes, healthy palate. And that's I take it it's supposed to support the view that the case is similar with beauty.

240
00:28:27,620 --> 00:28:34,430
Now, it's interesting question how much weight he's putting on this analogy. As I say, he's not so explicit about it.

241
00:28:34,430 --> 00:28:42,350
The implication may be that, well, what other standard could there be if there's a standard at all when you've got something that's not a property,

242
00:28:42,350 --> 00:28:47,270
the object, but rather in the mind. And yet there are standards.

243
00:28:47,270 --> 00:28:55,820
What are the standard? Could there be. Except the response of a person of a particularly specified kind.

244
00:28:55,820 --> 00:29:06,080
That may be the implication, as I say. So this is the thought that that's going to be the general shape of the standard of tastes.

245
00:29:06,080 --> 00:29:12,200
And then he argues for what these obstructions are in the case of taste.

246
00:29:12,200 --> 00:29:21,320
Number one, lack of what he calls delicacy and delicacy appears to be the ability to detect features that are hard to detect.

247
00:29:21,320 --> 00:29:27,350
So subtle features of an artwork. And this is relevant.

248
00:29:27,350 --> 00:29:32,600
Lack of delicacy is an obstruction because beautiful works often.

249
00:29:32,600 --> 00:29:38,750
Please. In virtue of hard to detect features.

250
00:29:38,750 --> 00:29:47,420
That's interesting why he thinks this. So again, he appeals to something that is a little bit a little bit quaint again.

251
00:29:47,420 --> 00:29:51,800
So he said he takes it to explain why it's possible to use general principles to

252
00:29:51,800 --> 00:29:58,700
convince somebody that something's beautiful when they didn't initially like it.

253
00:29:58,700 --> 00:30:05,900
So what he imagines is going on here is that we show a person some feature which is known to please universally.

254
00:30:05,900 --> 00:30:15,950
So there's a principle that says anything with this feature, please universally and which pleases him when it's present in a high degree.

255
00:30:15,950 --> 00:30:26,030
And we point out that it's present in a small degree in the work that he doesn't like him, thinks he's got to agree that the thing is beautiful.

256
00:30:26,030 --> 00:30:28,280
And he says it wouldn't be possible,

257
00:30:28,280 --> 00:30:39,380
implies that is wouldn't be possible for this procedure to work or to be convincing if delicacy weren't needed to perceive beauty.

258
00:30:39,380 --> 00:30:41,550
You get the appropriate sentiment.

259
00:30:41,550 --> 00:30:50,930
As I say, this is a little quaint because he's so confident that you can argue somebody into agreeing with you about.

260
00:30:50,930 --> 00:30:57,680
About the beauty of an object. And as we'll see tomorrow, Kant explicitly denies this.

261
00:30:57,680 --> 00:31:02,630
And it's been a sort of one of the main questions in aesthetics is whether you can establish

262
00:31:02,630 --> 00:31:07,520
that something is beautiful by any means other than seeing it and feeling something,

263
00:31:07,520 --> 00:31:14,390
whether an argument could actually be used to justify the view or even to prove the view that something's beautiful.

264
00:31:14,390 --> 00:31:27,150
As we'll see, Kant is going to deny this. Hume, again, strangely enough, take that for granted.

265
00:31:27,150 --> 00:31:36,210
In the course of trying to show the delicacy is relevant, next, obstruction is lack of practise.

266
00:31:36,210 --> 00:31:45,240
So practise here has two aspects. First of all, the critic needs practise contemplating other artworks of the same kind.

267
00:31:45,240 --> 00:31:52,390
And as he puts it, other species of the same kind of beauty.

268
00:31:52,390 --> 00:31:58,350
And he says, if we don't have this, then our sentiments will be obscure and confused.

269
00:31:58,350 --> 00:32:04,380
We won't perceive the works merits. We won't know what kinds of merits they are.

270
00:32:04,380 --> 00:32:17,320
And we won't know how great merit each one is. All of this you can only detect if you have experience in other work artworks of that kind.

271
00:32:17,320 --> 00:32:26,610
That's one aspect of practise. As I say, another aspect is repeatedly perusing the work that you are attempting to judge.

272
00:32:26,610 --> 00:32:32,400
We don't do that, he says. You may not perceive the work's merits clearly.

273
00:32:32,400 --> 00:32:38,610
And an interesting passage, he says there is a flutter or hurry of thought that attends the first perusal of work.

274
00:32:38,610 --> 00:32:44,460
And he says that makes the sentiment a bit obscure. So you have to look at it repeatedly to stop.

275
00:32:44,460 --> 00:32:46,710
You thought from fluttering, I guess.

276
00:32:46,710 --> 00:32:55,260
But at least the thought is that your going to be better enabled to perceive the work's merits much more clearly.

277
00:32:55,260 --> 00:33:04,830
And furthermore, you can make sure that the beauty is not a superficial kind. Some kinds of beauty, please, at first viewing, but not at others.

278
00:33:04,830 --> 00:33:09,810
And again, if one of the marks of a genuinely beautiful object is that a campus,

279
00:33:09,810 --> 00:33:17,010
please, at different times and ages, that's going to be quite relevant.

280
00:33:17,010 --> 00:33:22,410
And into the mix, he throws the consideration that practise is the best way to acquire delicacy,

281
00:33:22,410 --> 00:33:30,270
which is one of the as we established necessary traits of a critic.

282
00:33:30,270 --> 00:33:34,640
So a third thing is what he describes as comparison.

283
00:33:34,640 --> 00:33:43,280
So if you're unable to compare a work with many others, then inferior works often see much better than they are.

284
00:33:43,280 --> 00:33:48,190
This is a bit similar to John Stewart Mills discussion of higher pleasures.

285
00:33:48,190 --> 00:33:54,080
This is how can you tell between two pleasures, whether one is higher than another, intrinsically better than another?

286
00:33:54,080 --> 00:33:58,390
The only way is to ask somebody who's experienced both and ask them which they prefer.

287
00:33:58,390 --> 00:34:09,830
And if they all agree that A is better than B than A is a higher pleasure and B, very similar thing going on here in this qualification of comparison.

288
00:34:09,830 --> 00:34:20,450
Fourthly, prejudice is an obstruction and prejudice is, he understands and a kind of idiosyncratic way.

289
00:34:20,450 --> 00:34:24,440
So he thinks that beautiful works can cause the appropriate sentiments only in people who

290
00:34:24,440 --> 00:34:32,060
put themselves in the mindset of the audience that the work was originally addressing.

291
00:34:32,060 --> 00:34:41,870
So give the example of oratory. So a speech in ancient times at any time, but particularly thinking of ancient orders,

292
00:34:41,870 --> 00:34:45,370
is addressed to a particular audience and for a particular purpose.

293
00:34:45,370 --> 00:34:49,670
And you won't be able to tell whether it's beautiful unless you put yourself in their shoes.

294
00:34:49,670 --> 00:34:58,530
That's what will enable the appropriate sentiment of beauty to come about.

295
00:34:58,530 --> 00:35:02,820
And more generally works addressed to other ages or cultures.

296
00:35:02,820 --> 00:35:08,280
He thinks you have to put yourself into the shoes of the people in those ages and cultures before you can

297
00:35:08,280 --> 00:35:14,880
tell whether the genuinely beautiful you test to see whether it pleases once you adopt their mindset.

298
00:35:14,880 --> 00:35:23,430
And interestingly as well, and this prefigures another thing in Kant, he thinks any work address to the public as opposed to,

299
00:35:23,430 --> 00:35:33,750
I guess, particular subset of the public is such that you must forget all things that are unique to you.

300
00:35:33,750 --> 00:35:39,000
And as he puts it, consider yourself as a man in general and see if it pleases you then.

301
00:35:39,000 --> 00:35:46,140
So his examples are if you're friends with the author or enemies of the author, forget that.

302
00:35:46,140 --> 00:35:50,880
Got to leave that aside and see if the work causes the sentiment of beauty.

303
00:35:50,880 --> 00:35:58,940
And you then it doesn't just scream so that things must read universally.

304
00:35:58,940 --> 00:36:03,330
Well, remember this. And this is one of the obstructions that keeps them from placing the claim earlier

305
00:36:03,330 --> 00:36:10,150
was only that they had the capacity to please universally and they will please.

306
00:36:10,150 --> 00:36:14,760
Conversely, if you're free of these obstructions and one of the obstructions is not putting

307
00:36:14,760 --> 00:36:21,870
yourself in the shoes of a man in general or the audience originally dressed,

308
00:36:21,870 --> 00:36:26,630
does that make sense? Wait, you're not supposed to put yourself in my shoes.

309
00:36:26,630 --> 00:36:32,130
I may be using a double negative here. Not putting yourself in those shoes isn't obstruction.

310
00:36:32,130 --> 00:36:34,680
So prejudice is an obstruction.

311
00:36:34,680 --> 00:36:43,170
What you ought to do is put yourself in the shoes of that person and that's how you get that'll be the appropriate test there.

312
00:36:43,170 --> 00:36:46,640
Does that make sense? Yeah. OK. Yeah.

313
00:36:46,640 --> 00:36:57,960
Surance. Yeah.

314
00:36:57,960 --> 00:37:05,670
So it would imply along with that, that over time, everyone can put themselves in the shoes of the original audience.

315
00:37:05,670 --> 00:37:09,930
When you put those two plans together. Well, that's right. And isn't consciously putting themselves in.

316
00:37:09,930 --> 00:37:14,850
Somebody should be somebody ready to move and just read it. And still enjoys it.

317
00:37:14,850 --> 00:37:20,640
She's not saying it can't. Please. If you don't do this. But that's not the standard of taste.

318
00:37:20,640 --> 00:37:25,800
To the standard of taste is if it does, please, when you do, put yourself in their shoes.

319
00:37:25,800 --> 00:37:29,880
The other kinds of pleasure are not really relevant to determine whether it's beautiful.

320
00:37:29,880 --> 00:37:39,290
And other questions can be intended.

321
00:37:39,290 --> 00:37:48,810
Why? Well, that's a good point.

322
00:37:48,810 --> 00:37:55,320
I mean, I don't think it relies on the claim that every but no work of art is written for the world.

323
00:37:55,320 --> 00:38:00,630
It does rely on the claim that at least some works of art are not written for the whole world.

324
00:38:00,630 --> 00:38:04,260
They're written for some particular bit of it, and it's them.

325
00:38:04,260 --> 00:38:15,510
You have to relate to that case.

326
00:38:15,510 --> 00:38:22,650
Yes, the audience in general, in that case, he talks about the public and he seems to have in mind when he talks about a man in general,

327
00:38:22,650 --> 00:38:27,870
contemporary works, as opposed to more distant ones like that.

328
00:38:27,870 --> 00:38:30,990
I mean, this view prefigures. What was the intent?

329
00:38:30,990 --> 00:38:36,330
The view that it's about disinterested pleasure, what he's going to describe as a disinterested pleasure.

330
00:38:36,330 --> 00:38:45,120
It's not exactly the same as this, but it's going to prove to be an extremely influential view.

331
00:38:45,120 --> 00:38:49,630
And the final abstraction is lack of good sense.

332
00:38:49,630 --> 00:39:01,620
Kind of unsurprisingly, good sense is needed to discern the pleasing relations between the parts of the work.

333
00:39:01,620 --> 00:39:08,220
To see how well the work is fitted for its purpose and also to understand any reasoning

334
00:39:08,220 --> 00:39:17,220
that work contains good sense here just seems to be kind of a general intelligence.

335
00:39:17,220 --> 00:39:21,120
Here, it's also needed to free oneself from prejudice.

336
00:39:21,120 --> 00:39:27,240
He thinks this is another reason why you need it.

337
00:39:27,240 --> 00:39:37,470
So the thought is the standard of taste is the joint verdict of critics with these five characteristics,

338
00:39:37,470 --> 00:39:45,510
good sense, freedom from prejudice, comparison, practise and delicacy.

339
00:39:45,510 --> 00:39:50,440
Now, question arises. Here is how many disputes can this standard settle?

340
00:39:50,440 --> 00:39:58,830
Or is it supposed to settle? And he raised a number of considerations that are relevant to this.

341
00:39:58,830 --> 00:40:10,320
So. Obviously, we can only use this standard if we can identify critics who have these five characteristics.

342
00:40:10,320 --> 00:40:15,720
And he says maybe that'll be a problem.

343
00:40:15,720 --> 00:40:21,750
And that would not be so good because that would defeat the purpose of this whole project.

344
00:40:21,750 --> 00:40:29,940
But he says an advantage here is that whereas questions about the things, beauty, our questions of sentiment,

345
00:40:29,940 --> 00:40:34,350
the question of whether a person has these characteristics is a question of fact.

346
00:40:34,350 --> 00:40:38,640
So we don't determine whether somebody has these characteristics by having a sentiment.

347
00:40:38,640 --> 00:40:47,970
We determine it in the ordinary way or ways that we determine other questions of fact by assembling evidence, arguing about it.

348
00:40:47,970 --> 00:40:56,430
These sorts of things. So the great advantage we've ended up with is that we seem to be on firm ground again.

349
00:40:56,430 --> 00:41:03,600
Is you first identifying the standard way? Who has these characteristics and then find out what their verdict is.

350
00:41:03,600 --> 00:41:10,980
Then you can find out which things are genuinely beautiful and you think there's a number of ways of identifying them.

351
00:41:10,980 --> 00:41:15,120
So the soundness of their understanding, as he puts it, shows their good sense.

352
00:41:15,120 --> 00:41:21,510
So you can tell whether somebody is generally intelligent, quite apart from questions about beauty.

353
00:41:21,510 --> 00:41:28,770
So to if they point out some subtle features of a work that you didn't notice before and help you enjoy them,

354
00:41:28,770 --> 00:41:36,690
then you can tell while they're evidently have greater delicacy than I do.

355
00:41:36,690 --> 00:41:42,450
And he also, interestingly, talks about the ascendent which they acquire in society.

356
00:41:42,450 --> 00:41:47,730
So the lasting influence they have on society's tastes now,

357
00:41:47,730 --> 00:41:53,850
I think the reason he thinks that this is a way of telling who is a true critic relates

358
00:41:53,850 --> 00:42:02,670
to what he says before about how great works of art will last for a long time.

359
00:42:02,670 --> 00:42:11,820
So he says superficial work of art won't stay in favour for too too long, at least, as he puts it, in a civilised society.

360
00:42:11,820 --> 00:42:20,190
If a critic, then it's preferred certain works of art and those preferences stay durable.

361
00:42:20,190 --> 00:42:28,560
We can tell that guy was a true critic because his preferences wouldn't have stayed in favour if he had hit on bad works of art.

362
00:42:28,560 --> 00:42:37,710
He's got he's got good taste because his preferences have endured amongst society.

363
00:42:37,710 --> 00:42:43,680
So that's the thought about identifying them.

364
00:42:43,680 --> 00:42:56,190
But another point, and this is often misunderstood, is that there are some differences in sentiment that the standard can't be used to resolve.

365
00:42:56,190 --> 00:43:06,300
And then Hume is perfectly upfront about them, not about it not being able to be used for this purpose.

366
00:43:06,300 --> 00:43:14,100
So in particular, what happens if true critics differ in their sentiments about the same work?

367
00:43:14,100 --> 00:43:24,480
And Hume even thinks that this is bound to happen because he thinks that we can't help preferring an author who is similar to us,

368
00:43:24,480 --> 00:43:32,270
nor can we help referring works that portray customs that are familiar to us.

369
00:43:32,270 --> 00:43:38,720
And so he thinks the true critic won't be able to help, preferring works like this.

370
00:43:38,720 --> 00:43:47,300
And so you'll get to critics of different tent temperaments or from different cultures ranking the works differently.

371
00:43:47,300 --> 00:43:56,160
So one preferring his famous example of it to Tacitus, because he's a young man and his passions are warm and obied right.

372
00:43:56,160 --> 00:44:07,670
Love writes love poetry. Tacitus is a desiccated old historian, whereas 50 year old man prefers Tacitus.

373
00:44:07,670 --> 00:44:18,380
Now, the bit about this that's I say is often misunderstood is that and what's often not often remarked is that Hume is explicit,

374
00:44:18,380 --> 00:44:22,310
that he thinks differences of these kinds are only differences in the degree of

375
00:44:22,310 --> 00:44:27,530
pleasure that you can get that these true critics get from different works.

376
00:44:27,530 --> 00:44:36,890
So they're not cases of one true critic liking the work and another not liking the work.

377
00:44:36,890 --> 00:44:42,590
So it's not that the old guy doesn't like all of it at all.

378
00:44:42,590 --> 00:44:51,550
He gets the sentiment of beauty from Obied, but less intensely than he used to.

379
00:44:51,550 --> 00:44:53,620
So that's a very important qualification,

380
00:44:53,620 --> 00:45:03,040
because what it means is that the standard of taste is still perfectly good as a standard for determining which objects are beautiful.

381
00:45:03,040 --> 00:45:22,840
If he was right and his concession here isn't only that it doesn't always tell us or give an answer to how beautiful it is relative to another work.

382
00:45:22,840 --> 00:45:37,650
So there is no answer. There's no fact of the matter about in this case, whether it is better than Tacitus or vice versa.

383
00:45:37,650 --> 00:45:49,080
And the last feature of the essay that's again confuse a number of people is the discussion at the very end.

384
00:45:49,080 --> 00:45:59,460
So I think what he's doing here is providing examples of controversies that he thinks the standard of taste can settle.

385
00:45:59,460 --> 00:46:08,430
So amongst them, representing strange customs, he thinks if we accept the standard,

386
00:46:08,430 --> 00:46:15,150
we can show that representing strange or unfamiliar customs does not diminish the work's beauty.

387
00:46:15,150 --> 00:46:22,350
And the reason for that is that it doesn't stop a true critic from enjoying it, because remember the true critic free from prejudice.

388
00:46:22,350 --> 00:46:26,700
Now, why might somebody think that it does? I'm not really sure.

389
00:46:26,700 --> 00:46:34,980
But he, in connexion with this, refers to what was then called the dispute over the ancients versus the moderns,

390
00:46:34,980 --> 00:46:45,900
which was a dispute over whether modern learning had exceeded ancient learning, whether we knew more now than the Romans did or the Greeks.

391
00:46:45,900 --> 00:46:50,430
That was, again, very live dispute at the time.

392
00:46:50,430 --> 00:46:58,050
And so he thinks that his standard can shed some light on that kind of thing with that example.

393
00:46:58,050 --> 00:47:01,980
However, there's limits to this.

394
00:47:01,980 --> 00:47:10,590
So he thinks this standard also shows that immorality in a work does diminish its beauty.

395
00:47:10,590 --> 00:47:15,810
So at least if it is portrayed without condemning it.

396
00:47:15,810 --> 00:47:26,280
And the reason for that is that immorality, at least if you're a critic recognising recognise it cannot please the true critic.

397
00:47:26,280 --> 00:47:31,890
It can't cause a pleasurable sentiment in the true critic.

398
00:47:31,890 --> 00:47:44,330
And this is something that's puzzling a lot of people. This phenomenon, which has been called the puzzle of imaginative resistance.

399
00:47:44,330 --> 00:47:51,230
Why is it that artwork's can ask us to imagine that time travel is possible or

400
00:47:51,230 --> 00:47:56,360
that Alice went down the rabbit hole and had all kinds of these adventures?

401
00:47:56,360 --> 00:48:07,040
But we won't accept a world. We won't accept being asked to imagine a world in which genocide is OK or wanton cruelty is great.

402
00:48:07,040 --> 00:48:19,280
We don't seem to accept the request to imagine a world in which moral truths are radically different from what they are.

403
00:48:19,280 --> 00:48:26,090
So that's it's something that humans picked up on. And I think the point of mentioning it is to say that because of this one,

404
00:48:26,090 --> 00:48:33,230
please, that you're a critic and that shows that immorality diminishes beauty.

405
00:48:33,230 --> 00:48:43,070
And he closes by considering error, speculative errors. So he thinks errors, for example, in religion, with certain striking exceptions,

406
00:48:43,070 --> 00:48:48,530
don't diminish the work's beauty because everybody makes mistakes in religion and in philosophy.

407
00:48:48,530 --> 00:48:53,600
And it's not hard for a true critic to put himself in the shoes of somebody who's made those mistakes.

408
00:48:53,600 --> 00:49:02,600
So those mistakes don't diminish, don't prevent them from feeling pleasure with the one exception of superstition.

409
00:49:02,600 --> 00:49:08,840
He thinks superstition is particularly ridiculous or galling type of error,

410
00:49:08,840 --> 00:49:14,690
that the true critic won't be able to put his self into the mind set up or won't be able to get over.

411
00:49:14,690 --> 00:49:26,300
And I think he compared he closes by saying how ridiculous it is that Boccaccio thanks God and the ladies for protecting him,

412
00:49:26,300 --> 00:49:30,170
offering them their protection. That sort of thing.

413
00:49:30,170 --> 00:49:36,430
He thinks the trick critic just won't be able to get over. All right.

414
00:49:36,430 --> 00:49:45,950
So those are, I think, the main points that he makes here in the little time we have left.

415
00:49:45,950 --> 00:49:54,990
I'd like to mention just a few of the objections that have often been raised to this.

416
00:49:54,990 --> 00:49:58,290
One obvious objection is how does he know?

417
00:49:58,290 --> 00:50:13,200
And what kind of evidence has he given us that beautiful objects will please everybody with these five characteristics?

418
00:50:13,200 --> 00:50:26,770
Similarly, but this is a distinct point. How does he know the beautiful objects have the capacity to please everyone?

419
00:50:26,770 --> 00:50:39,970
Is that an empirical claim supported by experience or is it part of what it is to be beautiful, that it has the capacity to please everyone?

420
00:50:39,970 --> 00:50:51,460
As we'll see tomorrow? Thinks that it's the latter, that it's not an empirical claim that beautiful works have the capacity to please everyone.

421
00:50:51,460 --> 00:50:57,040
It's just part of what it is for something to be beautiful, that it has this capacity.

422
00:50:57,040 --> 00:51:04,390
Nothing could count as beautiful if it didn't have this capacity. So that raise an interesting question.

423
00:51:04,390 --> 00:51:16,150
How does Hume conceive of this claim? If you need to go now, you can, but I'm just going to mention one last objection,

424
00:51:16,150 --> 00:51:24,970
which is a pretty standard one, and that's the claim that the standard of taste is circular.

425
00:51:24,970 --> 00:51:34,570
So the objection goes that if indeed this is supposed to help us identify the beautiful objects,

426
00:51:34,570 --> 00:51:40,570
then to claim seems to be to identify beautiful objects. We need to identify true critics.

427
00:51:40,570 --> 00:51:48,220
But how do we identify your critics? They just seem to be the ones who, well, identify the beautiful objects correctly.

428
00:51:48,220 --> 00:51:58,070
So we've got to know that they've they've identified the beautiful objects correctly to know that they're the true critics.

429
00:51:58,070 --> 00:52:04,340
But that's what we wanted to find out in the first place, namely which objects are the beautiful objects.

430
00:52:04,340 --> 00:52:08,060
So we need to know that already before we can find out who's a true critic.

431
00:52:08,060 --> 00:52:15,740
Knowing who is a true critic is not going to help us find out which objects are beautiful.

432
00:52:15,740 --> 00:52:23,540
Now, Peter Kivi has written a well-known response to this objection, so he grants part of it.

433
00:52:23,540 --> 00:52:32,510
He thinks that we can't determine whether critics have practise or have comparison and have the ability to compare works,

434
00:52:32,510 --> 00:52:38,180
at least in the way Hume describes these characteristics, unless we already know which objects are beautiful.

435
00:52:38,180 --> 00:52:45,680
And that's because, Hume says practise involves contemplating other species of beauty and comparing a work with the

436
00:52:45,680 --> 00:52:52,340
several species of excellence that they've seen and to know whether they've seen those things.

437
00:52:52,340 --> 00:52:59,870
We've got to know whether those things are those things that they've seen are beautiful.

438
00:52:59,870 --> 00:53:03,440
However, the other three characteristics are not like this.

439
00:53:03,440 --> 00:53:12,560
So delicacy and Hume effectively makes this point something we can determine whether somebody is got whether we know what's beautiful or not.

440
00:53:12,560 --> 00:53:19,670
Good sense. Freedom from prejudice similarly seemed to avoid the circularity.

441
00:53:19,670 --> 00:53:27,320
Now, I myself don't really think the objection or Kev's response to it are successful.

442
00:53:27,320 --> 00:53:37,490
So take Kev's response. What it seems to require is that Hume drop the requirement of practise and comparison in good critics,

443
00:53:37,490 --> 00:53:45,620
and then he's left with the claim that beautiful objects will please anyone who has good sense,

444
00:53:45,620 --> 00:53:52,010
delicacy and is free from prejudice, regardless of how much practise they have with artworks,

445
00:53:52,010 --> 00:53:57,860
regardless of how much experience they have with works of art. And so that doesn't seem plausible.

446
00:53:57,860 --> 00:54:04,970
And if he were to adjust its position in that way, he would just end up with a new problem.

447
00:54:04,970 --> 00:54:10,520
He'd avoid the circularity objection. But he'd end up with the implausible claim that anybody delicate enough,

448
00:54:10,520 --> 00:54:18,080
intelligent enough and free from prejudice will be a standard of taste, will be a true critic.

449
00:54:18,080 --> 00:54:21,230
And that just doesn't seem plausible. You do need experience with artworks.

450
00:54:21,230 --> 00:54:28,580
A lot of the time in order to figure out which ones are good, if you can figure out which ones are good at all.

451
00:54:28,580 --> 00:54:34,520
However, I don't think that the circularity objection is a good objection either.

452
00:54:34,520 --> 00:54:47,270
So Hume doesn't assume that we can't identify any beautiful objects until we have the standard of taste.

453
00:54:47,270 --> 00:54:52,760
In fact, he assumes that we already know a number of examples which objects are beautiful.

454
00:54:52,760 --> 00:55:01,010
So he assumes that we can. We do know that Homer is beautiful and that Milton and Addison are superior.

455
00:55:01,010 --> 00:55:11,420
The objection represents him as saying that we're totally in the dark about which objects are beautiful until we get the standard of taste.

456
00:55:11,420 --> 00:55:16,550
But if we know that Homer is beautiful, Milton's beautiful Addison, it's beautiful.

457
00:55:16,550 --> 00:55:23,220
All of these things that we can tell whether a critic has practise as he read Homer, as he read Milton, as he read Addison.

458
00:55:23,220 --> 00:55:31,640
OK, well, that's good because we know that they're beautiful. What I think we have to return to is what he says about what a standard of taste is.

459
00:55:31,640 --> 00:55:44,960
It's a rule for resolving disputes. Hard cases in which we're not sure which of the two things are beautiful.

460
00:55:44,960 --> 00:55:58,819
It doesn't seem to be and it doesn't seem to be sold as a rule for determining which things, including the uncontroversial cases, are beautiful.

More from Lectionem

Featured on

Comment

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *